- History of the separation axioms
In
general topology , theseparation axiom s have had a convoluted history, with many competing meanings for the same term, and many competing terms for the same concept.Origins
Before the current general definition of
topological space , there were many definitions offered, some of which assumed (what we now think of as) some separation axioms. For example, the definition given byFelix Hausdorff in1914 is equivalent to the modern definition plus the Hausdorff separation axiom.The separation axioms, as a group, became important in the study of
metrisability : the question of which topological spaces can be given the structure of ametric space . Metric spaces satisfy all of the separation axioms; but in fact, studying spaces that satisfy only "some" axioms helps build up to the notion of full metrisability.The separation axioms that were first studied together in this way were the axioms for
accessible space s,Hausdorff space s,regular space s, andnormal space s. Topologists assigned these classes of spaces the names T1, T2, T3, and T4. Later this system of numbering was extended to include T0, T2½, T3½ (or Tπ), and T5.But this sequence had its problems. The idea was supposed to be that every Ti space is a special kind of Tj space if i > j. But this is not necessarily true. It depended on precisely how the definitions were phrased. For example, a regular space (called T3) does not have to be a Hausdorff space (called T2), at least not if you use the simplest definition of regular space.
Different definitions
Every author agreed on T0, T1, and T2. But for the other axioms, different authors could use radically different definitions, depending on what they were working upon. The reason why these differences could develop is that, if you assume that a topological space satisfies the T1 axiom, then the various definitions were (almost always) equivalent. Thus if you were going to make that assumption, then you would want to use the simplest definition. But if you did not make that assumption, then the simplest definition might not be the right one for the most useful concept; in any case, it would destroy the relation between Ti and Tj, allowing (for example) non-Hausdorff regular spaces.
Topologists working on the metrisation problem generally "did" assume T1; after all, all metric spaces are T1. Thus, they used the simplest definitions for the Ti. Then for those occasions when they did "not" assume T1, they used words ("regular" and "normal") for the more complicated definitions, in order to contrast them with the simpler ones. This approach reached its zenith in
1970 with the publication ofCounterexamples in Topology byLynn A. Steen andJ. Arthur Seebach, Jr. In contrast, general topologists, led by
John L. Kelley in1955 , usually did not assume T1, so they studied the separation axioms in the greatest generality from the beginning. Thus they used the more complicated definitions for Ti, so that they would always have a nice property relating Ti to Tj. Then for the simpler definitions, they used words (again, "regular" and "normal"). Both conventions could be said to follow the "original" meanings; the different meanings are the same for T1 spaces, which was the original context. But the result was that different authors used the various terms in precisely opposite ways. Adding to the confusion, some literature will observe a nice distinction between an axiom and the space that satisfies the axiom, so that a T3 "space" might need to satisfy the axioms T3 and T0 (e.g., in the "Encyclopedic Dictionary of Mathematics", 2nd ed.).Since 1970, the general topologists' terms have been growing in popularity, including in other branches of mathematics, such as analysis. (Thus we use their terms in Wikipedia.) But usage is still not consistent.
Regularity axioms
"
Kolmogorov quotient s,preregular space s, and the Ri sequence"Completely Hausdorff spaces
"T2½, the meaning of "completely", and Willard's switch"
References
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.