- Fitch's paradox of knowability
Fitch's paradox of knowability is one of the fundamental puzzles of
epistemic logic . It provides a challenge to the "knowability thesis", which states that any truth is, in principle, knowable. Theparadox is that this assumption implies the "omniscience principle", which asserts that any truth is, in actual fact, known. Essentially, Fitch's paradox asserts that the existence of an unknown truth is unknowable. So if all truths were knowable, it would follow that all truths are in fact known.The paradox is of concern for
verificationist oranti-realist accounts of truth, for which the "knowability thesis" is very plausible, but the omniscience principle is very implausible.The paradox appeared as a minor
theorem in a 1963 paper byFrederic Fitch , "A Logical Analysis of Some Value Concepts". Other than the knowability thesis, his proof makes only modest assumptions on the modal nature ofknowledge and of possibility. He also generalised the proof to different modalities. It resurfaced in 1979 whenW.D. Hart wrote that Fitch's proof was an "unjustly neglected logical gem".Proof
Suppose "p" is a sentence which is an "unknown truth"; that is, the sentence "p" is true, but it is not known that "p" is true. Then the sentence "the sentence "p" is an unknown truth" is true; and, since all truths are knowable, it would be possible to know that "p" is an unknown truth. But this isn't possible. If it were known that "p" is a truth, then it wouldn't be an "unknown" truth. Therefore, there are no unknown truths; equivalently (in
classical logic ), "all truths are known".This can be formalised with
modal logic . K and L will stand for "known" and "possible", respectively. Thus LK means "possibly known", in other words, "knowable". The modality rules used are:This time the proof proceeds:
The last line matches line 6 in the previous proof, and the remainder goes as before. So if any true sentence could possibly be believed by a rational person, then that person does believe all true sentences.
Some anti-realists advocate the use of
intuitionistic logic ; however, except for the very last line which moves from "there are no unknowable truths" to "all truths are known", the proof is, in fact, intuitionistically valid.The knowability thesis
Rule (C) is generally held to be at fault rather than any of the other logical principles employed. It may be contended that this rule does not faithfully translate the idea that all truths are knowable, and that rule (C) should not apply unrestrictedly. Kvanvig contends that this represents an illicit substitution into a modal context.
See also
*
Moore's paradox External links
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/fitch-paradox/ Fitch's Paradox of Knowability] . Article at the
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy , by Berit Brogaard and Joe Salerno.
* [http://consequently.org/writing/notevery/ Not Every Truth Can Be Known: at least, not all at once] . Discussion page on an article of the same name byGreg Restall to appear in Salerno's bookReferences
* Frederick Fitch, " [http://www.jstor.org/pss/2271594 A Logical Analysis of Some Value Concepts] ".
Journal of Symbolic Logic Vol. 28, No. 2 (Jun., 1963), pp. 135-142
* W. D. Hart. "The Epistemology of Abstract Objects", Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 53, 1979, pp. 153--65.
* Johnathan Kvanvig. [http://books.google.ca/books?id=nhRZqgREEQMC The Knowability Paradox] . Oxford University Press, 2006.
* Joe Salerno, ed. [http://knowability.googlepages.com/home New essays on the knowability paradox] . Oxford University Press, to appear.
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.