- Begriffsschrift
"Begriffsschrift" is the title of a short book on
logic byGottlob Frege , published in1879 , and is also the name of theformal system set out in that book."Begriffsschrift" is usually translated as "concept writing" or "concept notation"; the full title of the book identifies it as "a
formula language , modelled on that ofarithmetic , of purethought ." The "Begriffsschrift" was arguably the most important publication inlogic sinceAristotle founded the subject. Frege's motivation for developing his formal approach to logic resembledLeibniz 's motivation for hiscalculus ratiocinator . Frege went on to employ his logical calculus in his research on thefoundations of mathematics , carried out over the next quarter century.Notation and the system
The calculus contains the first appearance of quantified variables, and is essentially classical bivalent
second-order logic with identity, albeit presented using a highly idiosyncratic two-dimensional .In the first chapter, Frege defines basic ideas and notation, like proposition ("judgement"), the universal quantifier ("the generality"), the conditional, negation and the "sign for identity of content" ; in the second chapter he declares nine formalized propositions as axioms.
In chapter 1, §5, Frege defines the conditional as follows:
:"Let A and B refer to judgeable contents, then the four possibilities are:Let{| border=0 cellpadding=0 cellspacing=0 align=center
-
:signify that the third of those possibilities does not obtain, but one of the three others does. So if we negate , that means the third possibility is valid, i.e. we negate A and assert B."The calculus in Frege's work
Frege declared nine of his propositions to be
axiom s, and justified them by arguing informally that, given their intended meanings, they express intuitive truths. Re-expressed in contemporary notation, these axioms are:#
#
#
#
#
#
#
#
#These are propositions 1, 2, 8, 28, 31, 41, 52, 54, and 58 in the "Begriffschrifft". (1)-(3) govern
material implication , (4)-(6)negation , (7) and (8)identity , and (9) theuniversal quantifier . (7) expressesLeibniz 's indiscernibility of identicals, and (8) asserts that identity isreflexive .All other propositions are deduced from (1)-(9) by invoking any of the following
inference rule s:
*Modus ponens allows us to infer from and ;
*The rule of generalization allows us to infer from if "x" does not occur in "P";
*The rule of substitution, which Frege does not state explicitly. This rule is much harder to articulate precisely than the two preceding rules, and Frege invokes it in ways that are not obviously legitimate.The main results of the third chapter, titled "Parts from a general series theory," concern what is now called the ancestral of a relation "R". "b" is an "R"-ancestor of "a" is written "aR"*"b".
Frege applied the results from the "Begriffsschrifft", including those on the ancestral of a relation, in his later work "
The Foundations of Arithmetic ". Thus, if we take "xRy" to be the relation "y"="x"+1, then 0"R"*y is the predicate "y" is a natural number." (133) says that if "x", "y", and "z" arenatural number s, then one of the following must hold: "x"<"y", "x"="y", or "y"<"x". This is the so-called "law oftrichotomy ".Influence on other works
For a careful recent study of how the "Begriffsschrift" was reviewed in the German mathematical literature, see Vilko (1998). Some reviewers, especially
Ernst Schroder , were on the whole favorable. All work in formal logic subsequent to the "Begriffsschrift" is indebted to it, because its second-order logic was the first formal logic capable of representing a fair bit of mathematics and natural language.Some vestige of Frege's notation survives in the "turnstile" symbol derived from his "Inhaltsstrich" ── and "Urteilsstrich" │. Frege used these symbols in the "Begriffsschrift" in the unified form ├─ for declaring that a proposition is (tautologically) true. He used the "Definitionsdoppelstrich" │├─ as a sign that a proposition is a definition. Furthermore, the negation sign can be read as a combination of the horizontal "Inhaltsstrich" with a vertical negation stroke. This negation symbol was introduced by
Arend Heyting [Arend Heyting: "Die formalen Regeln der intuitionistischen Logik," in: "Sitzungsberichte der preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, phys.-math. Klasse", 1930, S. 42-65.] in 1930 to distinguishintuitionistic from classical negation.In the "
Tractatus Logico Philosophicus ",Ludwig Wittgenstein pays homage to Frege by employing the term "Begriffsschrift" as a synonym for logical formalism.Frege's 1892 essay, "
Sense and reference " recants some of the conclusions of the "Begriffschrifft" about identity (denoted in mathematics by the = sign).A quote
"If the task of philosophy is to break the domination of words over the human mind [...] , then my concept notation, being developed for these purposes, can be a useful instrument for philosophers [...] I believe the cause of logic has been advanced already by the invention of this concept notation." (Preface to the "Begriffsschrift")
ee also
*
Ancestral relation
*Frege's propositional calculus References
Further reading
*
Gottlob Frege . "Begriffsschrift: eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens". Halle, 1879.Translations:
* [http://www.southernct.edu/organizations/rccs/staff.html Bynum, Terrell Ward,] trans. and ed., 1972. "Conceptual notation and related articles", with a biography and introduction. Oxford Uni. Press.
*Bauer-Mengelberg, Stefan, 1967, "Concept Script" inJean Van Heijenoort , ed., "From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931". Harvard Uni. Press.Secondary literature:
* George Boolos, 1985. "Reading the "Begriffsschrift", "Mind" 94: 331-44.
*Ivor Grattan-Guinness , 2000. "In Search of Mathematical Roots". Princeton University Press.
* Risto Vilkko, 1998, " [http://www.sciencedirect.com/science?_ob=PublicationURL&_cdi=6817&_pubType=J&_acct=C000007858&_version=1&_urlVersion=0&_userid=103118&md5=cdca08d0984650f66659ab072801d527&jchunk=25#25 The reception of Frege's "Begriffsschrift",] " "Historia Mathematica 25(4)": 412-22.External links
*
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy : " [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/frege-logic/ Frege's Logic, Theorem, and Foundations for Arithmetic] " -- byEdward N. Zalta .
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.