Transcendental arguments

Transcendental arguments

A transcendental argument is a philosophical argument that starts from what a person experiences, and then deduces what must be the case for the person to have that experience.Baggini, Julian and Peter S. Fosl. 2003. '2.10 Transcendental arguments'. In "The Philosopher's Toolkit: A compendium of philosophical concepts and methods". Oxford: Blackwell Publishing]

Transcendental arguments explained

Transcendental arguments begin with an apparently indubitable and universally accepted statement about people's experiences of the world, and use this to make substantive knowledge-claims about the world.

Use of transcendental arguments

Transcendental arguments are often used as arguments against skepticism.

Kant

Immanuel Kant developed one of philosophy's most famous transcendental arguments in his chapter 'On the Deduction of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding' in the "Critique of Pure Reason". [Kant, Immanuel. 1998. "Critique of Pure Reason". Translated and edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.] Kant attempted to use transcendental arguments to show that our experiences could not be as they are without the existence of, for example, time and space. [Kant, Immanuel. 1998. "Critique of Pure Reason". Translated and edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: B118]

Criticisms of transcendental arguments

The skeptics' response

As stated above, one of the main uses of transcendental arguments is to use one thing we can know, the nature of our experiences, to counter skeptics' arguments that we cannot "know" something about the nature of the world. There are two ways that the skeptic can reject the claim that transcendental arguments give us knowledge of the world; the skeptic can object to the premise of the argument - the claim that we know about the quality of our experiences, or object to claims that we can draw conclusions about the world from the characteristics of those experiences. First, a skeptic could respond to such transcendental arguments by claiming that the arguer cannot be sure that he is having particular experiences. The claim that a person cannot be sure about the nature of his or her own experiences may initially seem bizarre. However, the very act of thinking about or, even more, describing our experiences in words, involves interpreting them in ways that go beyond so-called 'pure' experience. Second, skeptics can object to the use of transcendental arguments to draw conclusions about the nature of the world by claiming that even if a person "does" know the nature of his or her experiences, the person cannot know that the reasoning from these experiences to conclusions about the world is accurate. No matter how justifiable transcendental arguments may be, when people use them, they can still reach false conclusions.

References

ee also

*Transcendental idealism


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать курсовую

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Transcendental argument for the existence of God — The Transcendental Argument for the existence of God (TAG) is an argument for the existence of God that attempts to show that logic, science, ethics (and generally every fact of human experience and knowledge) are not meaningful apart from a… …   Wikipedia

  • Transcendental idealism — is a doctrine founded by German philosopher Immanuel Kant in the eighteenth century. Kant s doctrine maintains that human experience of things consists of how they appear to us implying a fundamentally subject based component, rather than being… …   Wikipedia

  • Arguments for eternity — composed a particularly important area of philosophical debate among Greek, Jewish, Islamic, and Christian philosophers during the ancient and medieval periods. The foremost philosopher arguing for eternity was Aristotle. Those ascribing to… …   Wikipedia

  • Transcendental argument for the non-existence of God — The Transcendental Argument for the Non existence of God (also called TANG) was first proposed by Michael Martin in a 1996 article in New Zealand Rationalist Humanist . [http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/michael martin/martin… …   Wikipedia

  • metaphysics — /met euh fiz iks/, n. (used with a sing. v.) 1. the branch of philosophy that treats of first principles, includes ontology and cosmology, and is intimately connected with epistemology. 2. philosophy, esp. in its more abstruse branches. 3. the… …   Universalium

  • Psychology (The separation of) from philosophy — The separation of psychology from philosophy Studies in the sciences of mind 1815–1879 Edward S.Reed THE IMPOSSIBLE SCIENCE Traditional metaphysics The consensus of European opinion during and immediately after the Napoleonic era was that… …   History of philosophy

  • Existence of God — Part of a series on God General conceptions …   Wikipedia

  • Kant’s Copernican revolution — Daniel Bonevac Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason was to transform the philosophical world, at once bringing the Enlightenment to its highest intellectual development and establishing a new set of problems that would dominate philosophy in… …   History of philosophy

  • Argument — This article is about the subject as it is studied in logic and philosophy. For other uses, see Argument (disambiguation). In philosophy and logic, an argument is an attempt to persuade someone of something, by giving reasons or evidence for… …   Wikipedia

  • Transzendentalphilosophie — Der Begriff Transzendentalphilosophie umfasst philosophische Systeme und Ansätze, die die Grundstrukturen des Seins nicht durch eine Ontologie (Theorie des Seienden), sondern im Rahmen des Entstehens und Begründens von Wissen über das Sein… …   Deutsch Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”