- Phaedrus (dialogue)
The "Phaedrus" (Greek: Φαίδρος), written by
Plato , is a dialogue between Plato's mainprotagonist ,Socrates , and Phaedrus, an interlocutor in several dialogues. The "Phaedrus" was presumably composed around370 BC , around the same time as Plato's "Republic" and "Symposium"; with those two texts, it is often considered one of Plato's literary high points. Although ostensibly about the topic oflove , the discussion in the dialogue revolves around the art ofrhetoric and how it should be practiced, and dwells on subjects as diverse asreincarnation and erotic love.etting
Socrates runs into Phaedrus on the outskirts of Athens. Phaedrus has just come from the home of
Lysias , son ofCephalus , where Lysias has given a speech on love. Socrates, stating that he is "sick with passion for hearing speeches" rf|1|plato, walks into the countryside with Phaedrus hoping that Phaedrus will repeat the speech. They sit by a stream under a plane tree and a chaste tree, and the rest of the dialogue consists of oration and discussion.The dialogue, somewhat unusually, does not set itself as a re-telling of the day's events. The dialogue is given unmediated, in the direct words of Socrates and Phaedrus, without other interlocutors to introduce the story or give it to us; it comes first hand, as if we are witnessing the events themselves. This is in contrast to such dialogues as the "Symposium", in which Plato sets up multiple layers between the day's events and our hearing of it, explicitly giving us an incomplete, fifth-hand account.
Dramatis Personæ
[
Bodleian Library , written in AD895 .]
* Socrates
* Phaedrus
* Lysias (in absentia)Lysias was one of the three sons of Cephalus, the patriarch whose home is the setting for Plato's Republic. Lysias was perhaps the most famous "logo-graphos" - lit. "argument writer" - in Athens during the time of Plato. Lysias was a rhetorician and a sophist whose best-known extant work is a defense speech, "
On The Murder of Eratosthenes ." The speech is a masterpiece in which a man who murdered his wife's lover claims that the laws of Athens required him to do it. The outcome of this speech is unknown.ummary
The dialogue begins with a series of speeches on love; the second half consists of discussion on the nature and proper practice of love and rhetoric, encompassing discussions of the
soul , madness and divine inspiration, and the practice and mastery of anart .As they walk out into the countryside, Phaedrus agrees to recite for Socrates the speech of Lysias. Socrates, however, suspects strongly that Phaedrus has a copy of the speech with him. Saying that while Lysias is present, he would never allow himself to be used as a training partner for Phaedrus to practice his own speechmaking on, he asks Phaedrus to expose what he is holding under his cloak. Phaedrus gives in and agrees to read the speech as it is written.rf|2|plato2
Lysias' speech
They walk through a stream and find a seat in the shade, and Phaedrus commences to read aloud the speech. Beginning with "You understand, then, my situation: I've told you how good it would be for us in my opinion, if this worked out",rf|3|plato3 the speech proceeds to explain all the reasons why it is better for a boy to give his favor to an older suitor who does "not" love him, rather than one who does. Friendship with a non-lover, he says, will last longer; it will be based on intellect rather than looks, will be honest rather than based in false flattery, and a dispassionate lover will not abandon his friend for another boy. Conversely, the boy will not be giving his favor to someone who is "more sick than sound in the head" and is not thinking straight, overcome by love. Finally, Lysias explains that it is best to give one's favor to one who can best return it, rather than one who needs it most.rf|4|plato4
Socrates declares that he is in ecstasy, and furthermore, it is all Phaedrus' doing. As the speech seemed to make Phaedrus radiant, and Socrates is sure that Phaedrus understands these things better than he does himself, he followed Phaedrus' lead and shared in his Bacchic frenzy. Phaedrus asks Socrates not to joke.rf|5|plato5
Socrates then admits that he thought the preceding speech was terrible. It repeated itself numerous times, seemed uninterested in its subject, and seemed to be showing off. He then says he can make an even better speech than Lysias on the same subject.rf|6|plato6
First speech of Socrates
Socrates, however, refuses to give the speech. Phaedrus warns him that he is younger and stronger, and Socrates should "take his meaning" and "stop playing hard to get".rf|7|plato7 After finally swearing on the plane tree that he will never recite another speech to Socrates if Socrates refuses, Socrates, covering his head out of embarrassment, consents.rf|8|plato8
Socrates, rather than simply listing reasons as Lysias had done, begins by explaining that while all men desire beauty, some are in love and some are not. We are all ruled, he says, by two principles: one is our inborn desire for pleasure, and the other is our acquired judgment that pursues what is best (237d). Following your judgment is "being in your right mind", while following desire towards pleasure without reason is "outrage" "(hybris)".rf|9|plato9
Following different desires leads to different things; one who follows his desire for food is a glutton, and so on. The desire to take pleasure in beauty, reinforced by the kindred beauty in human bodies, is called "Eros".rf|10|plato10
Remarking that he is in the grip of something divine, and may soon be overtaken by the madness of the
nymph s in this place,rf|11|plato11 he goes on.The problem, he explains, is that one overcome with this desire will want to turn his boy into whatever is most pleasing to himself, rather than what is best for the boy.rf|12|plato12 The boy's intellectual progress will be stifled,rf|13|plato13 his physical condition will suffer,rf|14|plato14 the lover will not wish the boy to mature and take a family,rf|15|plato15 all because the lover is shaping him out of desire for pleasure rather than what is best. At some point, "right-minded reason" will take the place of "the madness of love",rf|16|plato16 and the lover's oaths and promises to his boy will be broken.
The non-lover, he concludes, will do none of this, always ruled by judgment rather than desire for pleasure. Socrates, fearing that the nymphs will take complete control of him if he continues, states that he is going to leave before Phaedrus makes him "do something even worse".rf|17|plato17
However, just before Socrates is about to leave, he is stopped by the "familiar divine sign", his
daemon , which occurs always and only just before Socrates is about to do something he should not. A voice "from this very spot" forbids Socrates to leave before he makes atonement for some offense to the gods. Socrates states that he is a "seer". While he is not very good at it, he is good enough for his purposes, and he recognizes what his offense has been: if love is a god or something divine, as he and Phaedrus both agree he is, he cannot be bad, as the previous speeches have portrayed him.rf|18|plato18 Socrates, baring his head, vows to undergo a rite of purification as a follower of theMuse s, and proceeds to give a speech praising the lover.rf|19|plato19econd speech of Socrates
Madness
Socrates begins by discussing madness. If madness is all bad, then the preceding speeches would have been correct, but in actuality, madness given as a gift of the gods provides us with some of the best things we have.rf|20|plato20There are, in fact, four kinds of divine madness:
#FromApollo , the gift of prophecy;
#FromDionysus , the mystic rites and relief from present hardship;
#From the Muses, poetry;
#FromAphrodite , love.As they must show that the madness of love is, indeed, sent by a god to benefit the lover and beloved in order to disprove the preceding speeches, Socrates embarks on a proof of the divine origin of this fourth sort of madness. It is a proof, he says, that will convince "the wise if not the clever".rf|21|plato21
The soul
He begins by briefly proving the immortality of the soul. A soul is always in motion and as a
self-mover has no beginning. A self-mover is itself the source of everything else that moves. So, by the same token, it cannot be destroyed. Bodily objects moved from the outside have no soul, while those that move from within have a soul. Moving from within, all souls are self-movers, and hence their immortality is necessary.rf|22|plato22Then begins the famous Chariot allegory, called by R. Hackworth the "centrepiece" of "Phaedrus", and "the famous and moving account of the vision, fall and incarnation of the soul". A soul, says Socrates, is like the "natural union of a team of winged horses and their charioteer". While the gods have two good horses, everyone else has a mixture: one is beautiful and good, while the other is neither.rf|24|plato24
As souls are immortal, those lacking bodies patrol all of heaven so long as their wings are in perfect condition. When a soul sheds its wings, it comes to earth and takes on an earthly body which then seems to move itself.rf|25|plato25These wings lift up heavy things to where the gods dwell, and are nourished and grow in the presence of the wisdom, goodness, and beauty of the divine. However, foulness and ugliness make the wings shrink and disappear.rf|26|plato26
In heaven, he explains, there is a procession led by
Zeus , who looks after everything and puts things in order. All of the gods, with the exception ofHestia , follow Zeus in this procession. While the chariots of the gods are balanced and easier to control, other charioteers must struggle with their bad horse, which will drag them down to earth if it has not been properly trained.rf|27|plato27 As the procession works its way upward, it eventually makes it up to the high ridge of heaven, where the gods take their stands, are taken in a circular motion and gaze at all that is beyond heaven.rf|28|plato28What is outside of heaven, says Socrates, is quite difficult to describe, lacking color, shape, or solidity, as it is the subject of all true knowledge, visible only to intelligence.rf|29|plato29 The gods delight in these things and are nourished. Feeling wonderful, they are taken around until they make a complete circle. On the way they are able to see Justice, Self-Control, Knowledge, and other things as they are in themselves, unchanging. When they have seen all things and feasted on them, coming all the way around, they sink back down inside heaven.rf|30|plato30
The immortal souls that follow the gods most closely are able to just barely raise their chariots up to the rim and look out on Reality. They see some things and miss others, having to deal with their horses; they rise and fall at varying times. Other souls, while straining to keep up, are unable to rise, and in noisy, sweaty discord they leave uninitiated, not having seen reality. Where they go after is then dependent on their own opinions, rather than the truth. Any soul that catches sight of any one true thing is granted another circuit where it can see more; eventually, all souls fall back to earth. Those that have been initiated are put into varying human incarnations, depending on how much they have seen; those made into philosophers have seen the most, while kings, statesmen, doctors, prophets, poets, manual laborers,
sophist s, and tyrants follow respectively.rf|31|plato31Souls then begin cycles of
reincarnation . It generally takes 10,000 years for a soul to grow its wings and return to where it came, but philosophers, after having chosen such a life three times in a row, grow their wings and return after only 3,000 years. This is because they have seen the most and always keep its memory as close as possible, and philosophers maintain the highest level of initiation. They ignore human concerns and are drawn towards the divine. While ordinary people rebuke them for this, they are unaware that the lover of wisdom is possessed by a god. This is the fourth sort of madness, that of love.rf|32|plato32The madness of love
One comes to manifest this sort of love after seeing beauty here on earth and being reminded of true beauty as it was seen beyond heaven. When reminded, the wings begin to grow back, but as they are not yet able to rise, the afflicted gaze aloft and pay no attention to what goes on below, bringing on the charge of madness. This is the best form that possession by a god can take, for all those connected to it.rf|33|plato33
When one is reminded of true beauty by the sight of a beautiful boy, he is called a lover. While all have seen reality, as they must have to be human, not all are so easily reminded of it. Those that can remember are startled when they see a reminder, and are overcome with the memory of beauty.rf|34|plato34
Beauty, he states, was among the most radiant things to see beyond heaven, and on earth it sparkles through vision, the clearest of our senses. Some have not been recently initiated, and mistake this reminder for beauty itself and pursue pleasure and procreating. This pursuit of pleasure, then, even when manifested in the love of beautiful bodies, is not "divine" madness, but rather just having lost one's head. The recent initiates, on the other hand, are overcome when they see a bodily form that has captured true Beauty well, and their wings begin to grow. When this soul looks upon the beautiful boy it experiences the utmost joy; when separated from the boy, intense pain and longing occur, and the wings begin to harden. Caught between these two feelings, the lover is in utmost anguish, with the boy the only doctor for the pain.rf|35|plato35
Socrates then returns to the myth of the chariot. The charioteer is filled with warmth and desire as he gazes into the eyes of the one he loves. The good horse is controlled by its sense of shame, but the bad horse, overcome with desire, does everything it can to go up to the boy and suggest to it the pleasures of
sex . The bad horse eventually wears out its charioteer and partner, and drags them towards the boy; yet when the charioteer looks into the boy's face, his memory is carried back to the sight of the forms of Beauty and Self-control he had with the gods, and pulls back violently on the reins. As this occurs over and over, the bad horse eventually becomes obedient and finally dies of fright when seeing the boy's face, allowing the lover's soul to follow the boy in reverence and awe.rf|36|plato36The lover now pursues the boy. As he gets closer to his quarry, and the love is reciprocated, the opportunity for sexual contact again presents itself. If the lover and beloved surpass this desire they have won the "true Olympic Contests"; it is the perfect combination of human self control and divine madness, and after death, their souls return to heaven.rf|37|plato37Those who give in do not become weightless, but they are spared any punishment after their death, and will eventually grow wings together when the time comes.rf|38|plato38
A lover's friendship is divine, Socrates concludes, while that of a non-lover offers only cheap, human dividends, and tosses the soul about on earth for 9,000 years. He apologizes to the gods for the previous speeches, and Phaedrus joins him in the prayer.rf|39|plato39
Discussion of rhetoric and writing
After Phaedrus concedes that this speech was certainly better than any Lysias could compose, they begin a discussion of the nature and uses of rhetoric itself. After showing that speechmaking itself isn't something reproachful, and that what is truly shameful is to engage in speaking or writing shamefully or badly, Socrates asks what distinguishes good from bad writing, and they take this up.rf|40|plato40
Phaedrus claims that to be a good speechmaker, one does not need to know the truth of what he is speaking on, but rather how to properly persuade,rf|41|plato41 persuasion being the purpose of speechmaking and oration. Socrates first objects that an orator who does not know bad from good will, in Phaedrus's words, harvest "a crop of really poor quality".rf|42|plato42Yet Socrates does not dismiss the art of speechmaking. Rather, he says, it may be that even one who knew the truth could not produce conviction without knowing the art of persuasion;rf|43|plato43on the other hand, "As the Spartan said, there is no genuine art of speaking without a grasp of the truth, and there never will be".rf|44|plato44
They go on to examine this. They first determine that rhetoric, the art of persuasion, is one single art that governs all speaking.rf|45|plato45To practice this art of persuasion, even when one is persuading the audience to a falsehood, one draws their audience through similarities. To do this properly, whether to deceive or avoid deception, one must know the truth- precisely in what respects things are similar and different; without this knowledge, to make proper comparisons is impossible, and to do so can not be considered an art.rf|46|plato46
To acquire the art of rhetoric, then, one must make systematic divisions between two different kinds of things: one sort, like "iron" and "silver", suggests the same to all listeners; the other sort, such as "good" or "justice", lead people in different directions.rf|47|plato47 Lysias failed to make this distinction, and accordingly, failed to even define what "love" itself is in the beginning; the rest of his speech appears thrown together at random, and is, on the whole, very poorly constructed.rf|48|plato48Socrates then goes on to say,:"Every speech must be put together like a living creature, with a body of its own; it must be neither without head nor without legs; and it must have a middle and extremities that are fitting both to one another and to the whole work."rf|49|plato49
Socrates's speech, on the other hand, starts with a thesis and proceeds to make divisions accordingly, finding divine love, and setting it out as the greatest of goods. And yet, they agree, the art of making these divisions is
dialectic , not rhetoric, and it must be seen what part of rhetoric may have been left out.rf|50|plato50When Socrates and Phaedrus proceed to recount the various tools of speechmaking as written down by the great orators of the past, starting with the "Preamble" and the "Statement Facts" and concluding with the "Recapitulation", Socrates states that the fabric seems a little threadbare.rf|51|plato51He goes on to compare one with only knowledge of these tools to a doctor who knows how to raise and lower a body's temperature but does not know when it is good or bad to do so, stating that one who has simply read a book or came across some potions knows nothing of the art.rf|52|plato52One who knows how to compose the longest passages on trivial topics or the briefest passages on topics of great importance is similar, when he claims that to teach this is to impart the knowledge of composing tragedies; if one were to claim to have mastered
harmony after learning the lowest and highest notes on thelyre , a musician would say that this knowledge is what one must learn before one masters harmony, but it is not the knowledge of harmony itself.rf|53|plato53This, then, is what must be said to those who attempt to teach the art of rhetoric through "Preambles" and "Recapitulations"; they are ignorant of dialectic, and teach only what is necessary to learn as preliminaries.rf|54|plato54Rhetoric, then, must determine the nature of the soul to be an art, just as medicine must determine the nature of the body; it must know the different types of souls and how they are moved.rf|55|plato55 And yet, Socrates says, the truth is of no import in a law court, but rather the convincing; rhetoric, people claim, consists of cleaving towards the likely and should leave the truth aside. However, as it has already been determined that only people that know the truth can properly use the art of the "likely", this popular opinion is decided to be clearly wrong.rf|56|plato56
They go on to discuss what is good or bad in writing. Socrates tells a brief legend, critically commenting on the gift of writing from the Egyptian god Theuth to King Thamus, who was to disperse Theuth's gifts to the people of Egypt. After Theuth remarks on his discovery of writing as a remedy for the memory, Thamus responds that its true effects are likely to be the opposite; it is a remedy for reminding, not remembering, he says, with the appearance but not the reality of wisdom. Future generations will hear much without being properly taught, and will appear wise but not be so, making them difficult to get along with.rf|57|plato57
No written instructions for an art can yield results clear or certain, Socrates states, but rather can only remind those that already know what writing is about.rf|58|plato58 Furthermore, writings are silent; they cannot speak, answer questions, or come to their own defense.rf|59|plato59
Accordingly, the legitimate sister of this is, in fact, dialectic; it is the living, breathing discourse of one who knows, of which the written word can only be called an image.rf|60|plato60The one who knows uses the art of dialectic rather than writing::"The dialectician chooses a proper soul and plants and sows within it discourse accompanied by knowledge- discourse capable of helping itself as well as a the man who planted it, which is not barren but produces a seed from which more discourse grows in the character of others. Such discourse makes the seed forever immortal and renders the man who has it happy as any human being can be."rf|61|plato61
To be a proper rhetorician, then, one must know the truth of what he is speaking or writing on and how to define and divide it until reaching something indivisible, one must understand the nature of the soul and what sort of speech is proper to each soul, and only then will he be able to use speech artfully, to teach or to persuade. This, he says, is the whole point of the argument they have been making.rf|62|plato62
You are only a true practitioner of the art of rhetoric, then, if you have:" . . . composed these things with a knowledge of the truth, if you can defend your writing when you are challenged, and if you can yourself make the argument that your writing is of little worth . . ."And furthermore,:"then you must be called by a name derived not from these writings but rather from those things that you are seriously pursuing . . . To call him wise, Phaedrus, seems too much, and proper only for a god. To call him wisdom's lover- a philosopher- or something similar would fit him better and be more seemly."rf|63|plato63
With the afternoon over and the heat dying down a bit, Socrates offers a short prayer to "dear Pan and all the other gods of this place", and they depart for the city.
Interpretations and themes
Madness and divine inspiration
In the Phaedrus, Socrates makes the rather bold claim that some of life's greatest blessings flow from madness; and he clarifies this later by noting that he is referring specifically to madness inspired by the gods. It should be noted that Phaedrus is Plato's only dialogue that shows Socrates outside the city of Athens, out in the country. It was believed that spirits and nymphs inhabited the country, and Socrates specifically points this out after the long
palinode with his comment about listening to thecicadas . After originally remarking that "landscapes and trees have nothing to teach me, only people do",rf|64|plato64 Socrates goes on to make constant remarks concerning the presence and action of the gods in general, nature gods such as pan and the nymphs, and the Muses, in addition to the unusually explicit characterization of his own daemon. The importance of divine inspiration is demonstrated in its connection with and the importance of religion, poetry and art, and above all else, love. Eros, much like in the "Symposium", is contrasted from mere desire of the pleasurable and given a higher, heavenly function. Unlike in the "Ion", a dialogue dealing with madness and divine inspiration in poetry andliterary criticism , madness here must go firmly hand in hand with reason, learning, and self-control in both love and art. This rather bold claim has puzzled readers and scholars of Plato's work for centuries because it clearly shows that Socrates saw genuine value in the irrational elements of human life, despite many other dialogues that show him arguing that one should pursue beauty and that wisdom is the most beautiful thing of all.Pederasty
The pederastic relationships common to ancient Greek life are also at the fore of this dialogue. In addition to theme of love discussed in the speeches, seeming
double entendre s and sexual innuendo is abundant; we see the flirtation between Phaedrus and Socrates as Phaedrus encourages Socrates to make his first speech, Phaedrus makes a remark at noon-time that Socrates should not leave as the heat has not passed and it is "straight-up, as they say,"rf|65|plato65 Socrates wishes to know what Phaedrus is holding under his cloak, and so on. The relationships discussed in the speeches are explicitly pederastic. And yet, this is tempered in various ways; role reversals between lover and beloved are constant, as they are in the "Symposium". Socrates, ostensibly the lover, exhorts Phaedrus to lead the way at various times, and the dialogue ends with Socrates and Phaedrus leaving as "friends"- equals, rather than partaking in the lover/beloved relationship inherent in Greek pederasty. In the beginning, they sit themselves under a chaste tree, which is precisely what its name suggests- often known as "monk's pepper", it was used by monks to decrease sexual urges and is believed to be anantaphrodisiac . Notably, Socrates sees the pederastic relationship as ideally devoid of sexual consummation; rather than being used for sexual pleasure, the relationship is a form of divine madness, helping both lover and beloved to grow and reach the divine.Rhetoric, philosophy, and art
The "Phaedrus" also gives us much in the way of explaining how art should be practiced. The discussion of rhetoric, the proper practice of which is found to actually be philosophy, has many similarities with Socrates's role as a "
midwife of the soul" in the "Theaetetus"; the dialectician, as described, is particularly resonant. To practice the art, one must have a grasp of the truth and a detailed understanding of the soul in order to properly persuade. Moreover, one must have an idea of what is good or bad for the soul and, as a result, know what the soul should be persuaded towards. To have mastered the tools of an art is not to have mastered the art itself, but only its preliminaries. This is much like the person who claims to have mastered harmony after learning the highest and lowest notes of the lyre. To practice an art, one must know what that art is "for" and what it can help one achieve.The role of divine inspiration in philosophy must also be considered; the philosopher is struck with the fourth kind of madness, that of love, and it is this divine inspiration that leads him and his beloved towards the good- but only when tempered with self-control.
Writing, examined separately but ultimately equated with philosophy and rhetoric, is somewhat deprecated; it is stated that writing can do little but remind those who already know, somewhat reminiscent of the archetypical
Zen master's admonishment that "those who know, know". Unlike dialectic and rhetoric, writing cannot be tailored to specific situations or students; the writer does not have the luxury of examining his reader's soul in order to determine the proper way to persuade. When attacked it cannot defend itself, and is unable to answer questions or refute criticism. As such, the philosopher uses writing "for the sake of amusing himself" and other similar things rather than for teaching others. A writer, then, is only a philosopher when he can himself argue that his writing is of little worth, among other requirements.This final critique of writing with which the dialogue concludes seems to be one of the more interesting facets of the conversation for those who seek to interpret Plato in general; Plato, of course, comes down to us through his numerous written works, and philosophy today is concerned almost purely with the reading and writing of written texts. It seems proper to recall that Plato's ever-present protagonist and ideal man, Socrates, fits Plato's description of the dialectician perfectly, and never wrote a thing.
There is an echo of this point of view in Plato's Seventh Epistle (Letter), wherein Plato says not to write down things of importance. rf|66|Plato66
See also
* The "Symposium"
* The "Republic"
* TheTheory of forms References
* Plato, "Phaedrus", trans. by Alexander Nehamas and Paul Woodruff. From "Plato: Complete Works", ed. by John M. Cooper. ISBN 0-87220-349-2, 228b (stph. p.)
*"Phaedrus" 228a-e
*"Phaedrus" 230e-231
*"Phaedrus" 231-234c
*"Phaedrus" 234d-e
*"Phaedrus" 235a, c
*"Phaedrus" 236c-d
*"Phaedrus" 236e-237
*"Phaedrus" 237e-238
*"Phaedrus" 238a-c
*"Phaedrus" 238c-d
*"Phaedrus" 238e
*"Phaedrus" 239c
*"Phaedrus" 239c
*"Phaedrus" 240a
*"Phaedrus" 241a
*"Phaedrus" 242a
*"Phaedrus" 242c-e
*"Phaedrus" 243a-b
*"Phaedrus" 244a
*"Phaedrus" 245c
*"Phaedrus" 245c-e
*"Phaedrus" 246a
*"Phaedrus" 246a-b
*"Phaedrus" 246c
*"Phaedrus" 246d-e
*"Phaedrus" 246e-247b
*"Phaedrus" 247b-c
*"Phaedrus" 247c
*"Phaedrus" 247d-e
*"Phaedrus" 247e-248e
*"Phaedrus" 248e-249d
*"Phaedrus" 249d-e
*"Phaedrus" 250a
*"Phaedrus" 250d-252b
*"Phaedrus" 253d-254e
*"Phaedrus" 255e-256b
*"Phaedrus" 256b-e
*"Phaedrus" 256e-257c
*"v" 258d
*"Phaedrus" 260a
*"Phaedrus" 260d
*"Phaedrus" 260d
*"Phaedrus" 260e
*"Phaedrus" 261e
*"Phaedrus" 262a-c
*"Phaedrus" 263b
*"Phaedrus" 263e-264b
*"Phaedrus" 264c
*"Phaedrus" 266c
*"Phaedrus" 266d-268a
*"Phaedrus" 268a-c
*"Phaedrus" 268c-e
*"Phaedrus" 269b-c
*"Phaedrus" 271a-272b
*"Phaedrus" 273d
*"Phaedrus" 274e-275b
*"Phaedrus" 275d-e
*"Phaedrus" 275e
*"Phaedrus" 276a
*"Phaedrus" 276e-277a
*"Phaedrus" 277b-c
*"Phaedrus" 278c-d
*"Phaedrus" 230d
*"Phaedrus" 242a
* Plato, "Seventh Epistle", "Therefore every man of worth, when dealing with matters of worth, will be far from exposing them to ill feeling and misunderstanding among men by committing them to writing." [http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/seventh_letter.html]ources
*Egan, Rory B. (1994). Cicada in Ancient Greece. Third issue, November 1994. http://www.bugbios.com/ced3/cicada_ancgrcult.html (accessed: November 26, 2007)
* [http://www.bugbios.com/ced3/cicada_ancgrcult.html]Bibliography
*Hackforth, R. (tr. and ed.). "Plato's Phaedrus". Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1972 (orig. vers. 1952). ISBN 0521097037.
External links
* [http://oll.libertyfund.org/index.php?option=com_staticxt&staticfile=show.php&title=111 Text (English and Greek) of "Phaedrus" (Fowler, 1925) at the Perseus Project]
* [http://oll.libertyfund.org/index.php?option=com_staticxt&staticfile=show.php&title=111 Text of "Phaedrus" (Jowett, 1892) with Introduction and running commentary]
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.