Peirce's law

Peirce's law

Peirce's law in logic is named after the philosopher and logician Charles Sanders Peirce. It was taken as an axiom in his first axiomatisation of propositional logic.

In propositional calculus, Peirce's law says that (("P"→"Q")→"P")→"P". Written out, this means that "P" must be true if there is a proposition "Q" such that the truth of "P" follows from the truth of if "P" then "Q". In particular, when "Q" is taken to be a false formula, the law says that if "P" must be true whenever it implies the false, then "P" is true. In this way Peirce's law implies the law of excluded middle.

Peirce's law does not hold in intuitionistic logic or intermediate logics and cannot be deduced from the deduction theorem alone.

Under the Curry-Howard isomorphism, Peirce's law is the type of continuation operators, e.g. call/cc in Scheme [ [http://citeseer.ist.psu.edu/griffin90formulaeastypes.html A Formulae-as-Types Notion of Control] - Griffin defines K on page 3 as an equivalent to Scheme's call/cc and then discusses its type being the equivalent of Pierce's law at the end of section 5 on page 9.] .

History

Here is Peirce's own statement of the law:: A "fifth icon" is required for the principle of excluded middle and other propositions connected with it. One of the simplest formulae of this kind is:: This is hardly axiomatical. That it is true appears as follows. It can only be false by the final consequent "x" being false while its antecedent ("x" —< "y") —< "x" is true. If this is true, either its consequent, "x", is true, when the whole formula would be true, or its antecedent "x" —< "y" is false. But in the last case the antecedent of "x" —< "y", that is "x", must be true. (Peirce, the "Collected Papers" 3.384).Peirce goes on to point out an immediate application of the law:: From the formula just given, we at once get:: where the "a" is used in such a sense that ("x" —< "y") —< "a" means that from ("x" —< "y") every proposition follows. With that understanding, the formula states the principle of excluded middle, that from the falsity of the denial of "x" follows the truth of "x". (Peirce, the "Collected Papers" 3.384).

Other proofs of Peirce's law

Showing Peirce's Law applies does not mean that "P"→"Q" or "Q" is true, we have that "P" is true but only ("P"→"Q")→"P", not "P"→("P"→"Q") (see affirming the consequent).

"simple proof:"(p ightarrow q) ightarrow p Rightarrowoverline{p ightarrow q} or p Rightarrowoverline{overline p or q} or p Rightarrow(p and overline q) or p Rightarrow(p and overline q) or (p and 1) Rightarrowp and (overline q or 1) Rightarrowp and 1 Rightarrowp.

Using Peirce's law with the deduction theorem

Peirce's law allows one to enhance the technique of using the deduction theorem to prove theorems. Suppose one is given a set of premises &Gamma; and one wants to deduce a proposition "Z" from them. With Peirce's law, one can add (at no cost) additional premises of the form "Z"→"P" to &Gamma;. For example, suppose we are given "P"→"Z" and ("P"→"Q")→"Z" and we wish to deduce "Z" so that we can use the deduction theorem to conclude that ("P"→"Z")→((("P"→"Q")→"Z")→"Z") is a theorem. Then we can add another premise "Z"→"Q". From that and "P"→"Z", we get "P"→"Q". Then we apply modus ponens with ("P"→"Q")→"Z" as the major premise to get "Z". Applying the deduction theorem, we get that ("Z"→"Q")→"Z" follows from the original premises. Then we use Peirce's law in the form (("Z"→"Q")→"Z")→"Z" and modus ponens to derive "Z" from the original premises. Then we can finish off proving the theorem as we originally intended.
**"P"→"Z" 1. hypothesis
***("P"→"Q")→"Z" 2. hypothesis
****"Z"→"Q" 3. hypothesis
*****"P" 4. hypothesis
*****"Z" 5. modus ponens using steps 4 and 1
*****"Q" 6. modus ponens using steps 5 and 3
****"P"→"Q" 7. deduction from 4 to 6
****"Z" 8. modus ponens using steps 7 and 2
***("Z"→"Q")→"Z" 9. deduction from 3 to 8
***(("Z"→"Q")→"Z")→"Z" 10. Peirce's law
***"Z" 11. modus ponens using steps 9 and 10
**(("P"→"Q")→"Z")→"Z" 12. deduction from 2 to 11
*("P"→"Z")→(("P"→"Q")→"Z")→"Z") 13. deduction from 1 to 12 QED

Completeness of the implicational propositional calculus

One reason that Peirce's law is important is that it can substitute for the law of excluded middle in the logic which only uses implication (see implicational propositional calculus). The sentences which can be deduced from the axiom schemas:
* "P"→("Q"→"P")
* ("P"→("Q"→"R"))→(("P"→"Q")→("P"→"R"))
* (("P"→"Q")→"P")→"P"
* from "P" and "P"→"Q" infer "Q"(where "P","Q","R" contain only "→" as a connective) are all the tautologies which use only "→" as a connective.

ee also

* Logical graph &mdash; Includes a graphic proof of Peirce's law.

Notes

References

* Peirce, C.S., "On the Algebra of Logic: A Contribution to the Philosophy of Notation", "American Journal of Mathematics" 7, 180–202 (1885). Reprinted, the "Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce" 3.359–403 and the "Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition" 5, 162–190.

* Peirce, C.S., "Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce", Vols. 1–6, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (eds.), Vols. 7–8, Arthur W. Burks (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1931–1935, 1958.

External links

* [http://planetmath.org/encyclopedia/PeircesLaw.html Peirce's Law] @ [http://planetmath.org/ PlanetMath] .

* [http://www.mywikibiz.com/Peirce's_law Peirce's Law] @ [http://www.mywikibiz.com MyWikiBiz] .


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать реферат

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Peirce's law — noun The classically valid but intuitionistically non valid formula of propositional calculus, which can be used as an substitute for the law of excluded middle in implicational propositional calculus …   Wiktionary

  • Peirce's law — The theorem of the propositional calculus stating that ((p →q ) →p ) →p …   Philosophy dictionary

  • Law of excluded middle — This article uses forms of logical notation. For a concise description of the symbols used in this notation, see Table of logic symbols. In logic, the law of the excluded middle states that the propositional calculus formula P ∨ ¬ P ( P or not P… …   Wikipedia

  • Law of noncontradiction — This article uses forms of logical notation. For a concise description of the symbols used in this notation, see List of logic symbols. In classical logic, the law of non contradiction (LNC) (or the principle of non contradiction (PNC), or the… …   Wikipedia

  • Peirce, Charles Sanders — American pragmatism Peirce Cheryl Misak INTRODUCTION Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914), one of America’s greatest philosophers, mathematicians, and logicians, was a difficult and not altogether pleasant character. That, combined with what the… …   History of philosophy

  • Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography — C. S. Peirce articles  General:    Charles Sanders Peirce Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography Philosophical:    Categories (Peirce) Semiotic elements and   classes of signs (Peirce) Pragmatic maxim • Pragmaticism… …   Wikipedia

  • Charles Peirce — Infobox Scientist name = Charles Peirce box width = image size = 200px caption = Charles Peirce birth date = September 10, 1839 birth place = Cambridge, Massachusetts death date = April 19, 1914 death place = residence = citizenship = nationality …   Wikipedia

  • Charles Sanders Peirce —  B …   Wikipedia

  • Schriften von Charles Sanders Peirce — Das nachfolgende Verzeichnis der Schriften von Charles Sanders Peirce dient als Ergänzung zum Verzeichnis der Werke von Peirce im Hauptartikel. Inhaltsverzeichnis 1 Vorbemerkung 2 Collected Papers 2.1 Vol. I. Principles of Philosophy …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Charles Peirce — Charles Sanders Peirce um 1870 Charles Sanders Peirce (* 10. September 1839 in Cambridge, Massachusetts; † 19. April 1914 in Milford, Pennsylvania) war ein US amerikanischer Mathematiker …   Deutsch Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”