- Slingshot argument
In
logic , a slingshot argument is one of a group of arguments claiming to show that alltrue sentences stand for the same thing.This type of argument was dubbed the "
slingshot " byphilosopher sJon Barwise and John Perry (1981) due to its disarming simplicity. Versions of the slingshot argument have been given byCharles Peirce ,Gottlob Frege ,Alonzo Church ,W. V. Quine , and Donald Davidson.Stephen Neale (1995) claims, controversially, that the most compelling version was suggested byKurt Gödel (1944).These arguments are sometimes modified to support the alternative, and evidently stronger, conclusion that there is only one "
fact ", or one true "proposition ", "states of affairs", "truth condition ", "truthmaker ", and so on.The argument
One version of the argument (Perry 1996) proceeds as follows.
Assumptions:
# Substitution. If two terms designate the same thing, then substituting one for another in a sentence does not change the designation of that sentence.
# Redistribution. Rearranging the parts of a sentence does not change the designation of that sentence, provided the truth conditions of the sentence do not change.
# Every sentence is equivalent to a sentence of the form "F"("a"). In other words, every sentence has the same designation as some sentence that attributes a property to something. (For example, "All men are mortal" is equivalent to "The number 1 has the property of being such that all men are mortal".)
# For any two objects there is a relation that holds uniquely between them. For example, if the objects in question are denoted by "a" and "b", the relation in question might be "R"("x", "y"), which is stipulated to hold just in case "x" = "a" and "y" = "b".)Let "S" and "T" be arbitrary true sentences, designating "Des"("S") and "Des"("T"), respectively. (No assumptions are made about what kinds of things "Des"("S") and "Des"("T") are.) It is now shown by a series of designation-preserving transformations that "Des"("S") = "Des"("T"). Here, "" can be read as "the "x" such that".
1. 2. assumption 3 3. redistribution 4. substitution, assumption 4 5. redistribution 6. redistribution 7. substitution, assumption 3 8. redistribution 9. assumption 3 Note that (1)-(9) is not a derivation of "T" from "S". Rather, it is a series of (allegedly) designation-preservating transformation steps.
Responses to the argument
As Gödel (1944) observed, the slingshot argument does not go through if
Bertrand Russell 's famous account ofdefinite description s is assumed. Russell claimed that the proper logical interpretation of a sentence of the form "The "F" is "G" is:: Exactly one thing is "F", and that thing is also "G".
Or, in the language of
first-order logic ::
When the sentences above containing -expressions are expanded out to their proper form, the steps involving substitution are seen to be illegitimate. Consider, for example, the move from (3) to (4). On Russell's account, (3) and (4) are shorthand for:
3'. 4'. Clearly the substitution principle and assumption 4 do not license the move from (3') to (4'). Thus, one way to look at the slingshot is as simply another argument in favor of Russell's theory of definite descriptions.
If one is not willing to accept Russell's theory, then it seems wise to challenge either "substitution" or "redistribution", which seem to be the other weakest points in the argument. Perry (1996), for example, rejects both of these principles, proposing to replace them with certain weaker, qualified versions that do not allow the slingshot argument to go through.
ee also
*
Abstraction
*Logic of information External links
* [http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=1117 Stephen Neale's "Facing Facts" reviewed by John Macfarlane]
References
* Barwise, Jon, and Perry, John (1981), "Semantic innocence and uncompromising situations", "Midwest Studies in the Philosophy of Language", VI.
* Gödel, Kurt (1944), "Russell's mathematical logic", in Schillp (ed.), "The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell", Evanston and Chicago: Northwestern University Press, pp. 125-53.
* Neale, Stephen (1995), "The philosophical significance of Gödel's Slingshot", "Mind", vol. 104, no. 416, pp. 761-825.
* Peirce, C.S. (1906), "Prolegomena to an Apology for Pragmaticism", "The Monist", 16, 492–546 (1906). Reprinted, "Collected Papers", CP 4.530–572.
* Perry, John (1996), "Evading the slingshot", in
Andy Clark et al. (eds.), "Philosophy and Cognitive Science", The Netherlands. [http://www-csli.stanford.edu/~john/PHILPAPERS/evading.pdf PDF]Bibliography
*
Charles Peirce (Bibliography)
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.