- Generalized game theory
Generalized game theory is an extension of
game theory to incorporatesocial theory concepts such asnorm , value, belief, role, social relationship, and institution. The theory was developed byTom R. Burns and has not had great influence beyond his immediate associates. The theory seeks to address certain perceived limitations of game theory by formulating a theory of rules and to incorporate more robust approach to socio-phsychological phenomena.In generalized game theory, games are conceptualized as
rule complex es, which is a set containing rules and/or other rule complexes. However, the rules may be imprecise, inconsistent, and even dynamic. The ways in which the rules may be changed is developed within the context of generalized game theory based on the principle of game transformation. This allows the rules themselves to be analyzed in complex ways, and thus the model more closely represents relationships and institutions discussed in thesocial science s. These types of games are sometimes called open games, that is, games which are open to transformation. Games which have specified, fixed players, fixed preference structures, fixed optimization procedures, and fixed action alternatives and outcomes are called closed games.Along the same lines, generalized game theory stresses the cultural institutional approach to game conceptualization and analysis (Baumgartner et al, 1975, see Burns, 2005). This is in contrast to conceptualization of games consisting of actors which are
autonomous utility maximizers. Further, the modeling of the actors themselves in generalized game theory is especially open to the use of concepts such asincomplete information andbounded rationality .Proponents of generalized game theory have advocated the application of the theory to
agent-based model ing,fuzzy game s,social evolution , andnew institutionalism , among others.Principles
Judgment in generalized game theory
A key aspect of actors decision making in generalized game theory is based on the concept of judgment. Several types of judgment could be relevant, for instance value judgment, factual judgment, and action judgment. In the case of action judgment, the actor seeks to take the course of action offered by the rules of the game which most closely fit the values held by the actor (where the values are a sub-rule complex of the game). Even the method by which the actor calculates closeness of fit can be controlled by the actors values (such as an actor might use a more speedy algorithm, or a more far-sighted one). The each actor has a judgment operator by which the actor can create a preference order of the perceived qualities of possible outcomes based on satisfying the condition that the qualities of the outcomes can be roughly said to be sufficiently similar to the qualities of the actors primary values or norms. Thus, in generalized game theory, each actor's judgment calculus includes the institutional context of the game (Burns, 2005).
General game solutions
A general or common game solution is a strategy or interaction order for the agents which satisfies or realizes the relevant norms and values of the players. This should lead to a state that is acceptable by the game players, and is not necessarily a normative equilibrium, but represents the "best result attainable under the circumstances" (Burns, 2005). Solutions may be reached through a sequence of proposed alternatives, and when the actors find the ultimate solution acceptable, the proposed solutions may be said to be convergent. Roszkowska and Burns (2002) showed that not every game has a common solution, and that divergent proposals may arise. This may result in a no equilibrium being found, and stems from dropping the assumption for the existence of a Nash equilibrium that the game that the game be finite or that the game have complete information. Another possibility is the existence of a rule which allows a dictator to force an equilibrium. The rules which make up the norms of the game are one way of resolving the problem of choosing between multiple equilibria, wuch as those arising in the so-called
folk theorem .Example: prisoner's dilemma
In the example of the two-player
prisoner's dilemma , for instance, proponents of generalized game theory are critical of therational Nash equilibrium wherein both actors defect because rational actors would be predisposed to work out coordinating mechanisms in order to achieve optimum outcomes. Although these mechanisms are not usually included in the rules of the game, generalized game theorists argue that they do exist in real life situations the prisoner's dilemma seeks to model. This is because there always exists a social relationship between the players characterized by rules and rule complexes. This relationship may be one of, for instance, solidarity (which results in thePareto optimal outcome), adversary (which results in the Nash equilibrium), or even hierarchy (by which one actor sacrifices their own good for the others benefit). Some values, such as pure rivalry, are seen as nonstable because both actors would seek asymmetric gain, and thus would need to either transform the game or seek another value to attempt to satisfy. If no communication mechanism is given (as is usual in the prisoner's dilemma), the social relationship between the actors is based on the actors own beliefs about the other (perhaps as another member of the human race, solidarity will be felt, or perhaps as a fellow criminal, adversary). This illustrates the principle of game transformation, which is a key element of the theory.References
*Baumgartner, T, Buckley, W, and Burns, T R (1975) "Relational Control: The Human Structuring of Cooperation and Conflict", Journal of Conflict Resolution, Vol. 19: 417-440
*Burns, Tom R and Roszkowska, Ewa (2005) "Generalized Game Theory: Assumptions, Principles, and Elaborations", Studies in Logic, Grammer, and Rhetoric, Vol. 8 (21)
*Roszkowska Ewa and Burns, T R (2002) Fuzzy Judgment in Bargaining Games: Diverse Patterns of Price Determination and Transaction in Buyer-Seller Exchange". Paper presented at the First World Congress of Game Theory, Bilbao, Spain, 2000. available [http://www.soc.uu.se/publications/fulltext/tb_/market-pricing-game.doc here (MSWord doc)] .
Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.