Constructivist analysis

Constructivist analysis

In mathematics, constructive analysis is mathematical analysis done according to the principles of constructivist mathematics.This contrasts with "classical analysis", which (in this context) simply means analysis done according to the (ordinary) principles of classical mathematics.

Generally speaking, constructive analysis can reproduce theorems of classical analysis, but only in application to separable spaces; also, some theorems may need to be approached by approximations.Furthermore, many classical theorems can be stated in ways that are logically equivalent according to classical logic, but not all of these forms will be valid in constructive analysis, which uses intuitionistic logic.

Examples

The intermediate value theorem

For a simple example, consider the intermediate value theorem (IVT).In classical analysis, IVT says that, given any continuous function "f" from a closed interval ["a","b"] to the real line "R", if "f"("a") is negative while "f"("b") is positive, then there exists a real number "c" in the interval such that "f"("c") is exactly zero.In constructive analysis, this does not hold, because the constructive interpretation of existential quantification ("there exists") requires one to be able to "construct" the real number "c" (in the sense that it can be approximated to any desired precision by a rational number).But if "f" hovers near zero during a stretch along its domain, then this cannot necessarily be done.

However, constructive analysis provides several alternative formulations of IVT, all of which are equivalent to the usual form in classical analysis, but not in constructive analysis.For example, under the same conditions on "f" as in the classical theorem, given any natural number "n" (no matter how large), there exists (that is, we can construct) a real number "c""n" in the interval such that the absolute value of "f"("c""n") is less than 1/"n".That is, we can get as close to zero as we like, even if we can't construct a "c" that gives us "exactly" zero.

Alternatively, we can keep the same conclusion as in the classical IVT -- a single "c" such that "f"("c") is exactly zero -- while strengthening the conditions on "f".We require that "f" be "locally non-zero", meaning that given any point "x" in the interval ["a","b"] and any natural number "m", there exists (we can construct) a real number "y" in the interval such that |"y" - "x"| < 1/"m" and |"f"("y")| > 0.In this case, the desired number "c" can be constructed.This is a complicated condition, but there are several other conditions which imply it and which are commonly met; for example, every analytic function is locally non-zero (assuming that it already satisfies "f"("a") < 0 and "f"("b") > 0).

For another way to view this example, notice that according to classical logic, if the "locally non-zero" condition fails, then it must fail at some specific point "x"; and then "f"("x") will equal 0, so that IVT is valid automatically.Thus in classical analysis, which uses classical logic, in order to prove the full IVT, it is sufficient to prove the constructive version.From this perspective, the full IVT fails in constructive analysis simply because constructive analysis does not accept classical logic.Conversely, one may argue that the true meaning of IVT, even in classical mathematics, is the constructive version involving the "locally non-zero" condition, with the full IVT following by "pure logic" afterwards.Some logicians, while accepting that classical mathematics is correct, still believe that the constructive approach gives a better insight into the true meaning of theorems, in much this way.

The least upper bound principle and compact sets

Another difference between classical and constructive analysis is that constructive analysis does not accept the least upper bound principle, that any subset of the real line R has a least upper bound (or supremum), possibly infinite.However, as with the intermediate value theorem, an alternative version survives; in constructive analysis, any "located" subset of the real line has a supremum.(Here a subset "S" of R is "located" if, whenever "x" < "y" are real numbers, either there exists an element "s" of "S" such that "x" < "s", or "y" is an upper bound of "S".)Again, this is classically equivalent to the full least upper bound principle, since every set is located in classical mathematics.And again, while the definition of located set is complicated, nevertheless it is satisfied by several commonly studied sets, including all intervals and compact sets.

Closely related to this, in constructive mathematics, fewer characterisations of compact spaces are constructively valid -- or from another point of view, there are several different concepts which are classically equivalent but not constructively equivalent.Indeed, if the interval ["a","b"] were sequentially compact in constructive analysis, then the classical IVT would follow from the first constructive version in the example; one could find "c" as a cluster point of the infinite sequence ("c""n")"n".

See also

* Indecomposability


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужно сделать НИР?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Analysis — (from Greek ἀνάλυσις , a breaking up ) is the process of breaking a complex topic or substance into smaller parts to gain a better understanding of it. The technique has been applied in the study of mathematics and logic since before Aristotle,… …   Wikipedia

  • Constructivist teaching methods — Constructivist teaching is based on constructivist learning theory. This theoretical framework holds that learning always builds upon knowledge that a student already knows; this prior knowledge is called a schema. Because all learning is… …   Wikipedia

  • Constructivist epistemology — is an epistemological perspective in philosophy about the nature of scientific knowledge[1]. Constructivists maintain that scientific knowledge is constructed by scientists and not discovered from the world. Constructivists claim that the… …   Wikipedia

  • Criticism of non-standard analysis — Non standard analysis and its offshoot, non standard calculus, have been criticized by several authors. The evaluation of non standard analysis in the literature has varied greatly. Joseph Dauben described it as a scientific revolution, while… …   Wikipedia

  • Philosophical analysis — (from Greek: Φιλοσοφική ανάλυση) is a general term for techniques typically used by philosophers in the analytic tradition that involve breaking down (i.e. analyzing) philosophical issues. Arguably the most prominent of these techniques is the… …   Wikipedia

  • Transactional analysis — [ thumb|right|Diagram of concepts in transactional analysis, based on cover of Eric Berne s 1964 book Games People Play.] Transactional analysis, commonly known as TA to its adherents, is an integrative approach to the theory of psychology and… …   Wikipedia

  • Constance Kamii — Dr. Constance Kamii is a Professor, Early Childhood Education Program Department of Curriculum and Instruction at the University of Alabama at Birmingham. Contents 1 Overview 2 The Harmful Effects of Algorithms in Grades 1 4 3 References …   Wikipedia

  • Paul Lorenzen — Infobox Scientist name=Paul Lorenzen birth date = March 24 1915 death date = October 1 1994 fields = Philosophy, MathematicsPaul Lorenzen (born March 24, 1915 in Kiel, Germany died October 1, 1994 in Göttingen, Germany) was a philosopher and… …   Wikipedia

  • Errett Bishop — Errett Albert Bishop (1928–1983) was an American mathematician known for his work on analysis. He is the father of constructivist analysis, by virtue of his 1967 Foundations of Constructive Analysis , where he proved most of the important… …   Wikipedia

  • Мягкая сила — Мягкая сила  форма политической власти, способность добиваться желаемых результатов на основе добровольного участия, симпатии и привлекательности, в отличие от «жёсткой силы», которая подразумевает принуждение. Содержание 1 Происхождение… …   Википедия

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”